The Blind Watchmaker (25 page)

Read The Blind Watchmaker Online

Authors: Richard Dawkins

Tags: #Science, #Life Sciences, #Evolution, #General

BOOK: The Blind Watchmaker
8.44Mb size Format: txt, pdf, ePub

Let us, for the sake of discussion, entertain the alternative assumption that life has arisen only once, ever, and that was here on Earth. It is tempting to object to this assumption on the following emotional grounds. Isn’t there something terribly medieval about it? Doesn’t it recall the time when the church taught that our Earth was the centre of the universe, and the stars just little pinpricks of light set in the sky for our delight (or, even more absurdly presumptuous, that the stars go out of their way to exert astrological influences on our little lives)? How very conceited to assume that, out of all the billions of billions of planets in the universe, our own little backwater of a world, in our own local backwater of a solar system, in our own local backwater of a galaxy, should have been singled out for life? Why, for goodness sake, should it have been
our
planet?

I am genuinely sorry, for I am heartily thankful that we have escaped from the small-mindedness of the medieval church and I despise modern astrologers, but I am afraid that the rhetoric about backwaters in the previous paragraph is just empty rhetoric. It is
entirely
possible that our backwater of a planet is literally the only one that has ever borne life. The point is that if there
were
only one planet that had ever borne life, then it would
have to
be our planet, for the very good reason that ‘we’ are here discussing the question! If the origin of life
is
such an improbable event that it happened on only one planet in the universe, then our planet has to be that planet. So, we can’t use the fact that Earth has life to conclude that life must be probable enough to have arisen on another planet. Such an argument would be circular. We have to have some independent arguments about how easy or difficult it is for life to originate on a planet, before we can even begin to answer the question of how many other planets in the universe have life.

But that isn’t the question we set out with. Our question was, how much luck are we allowed to assume in a theory of the origin of life on Earth? I said that the answer depends upon whether life has arisen only once, or many times. Begin by giving a name to the probability, however low it is, that life will originate on any randomly designated planet of some particular type. Call this number the spontaneous generation probability or SGP. It is the SGP that we shall arrive at if we sit down with our chemistry textbooks, or strike sparks through plausible mixtures of atmospheric gases in our laboratory, and calculate the odds of replicating molecules springing spontaneously into existence in a typical planetary atmosphere. Suppose that our best guess of the SGP is some very very small number, say one in a billion. This is obviously such a small probability that we haven’t the faintest hope of duplicating such a fantastically lucky, miraculous event as the origin of life in our laboratory experiments. Yet if we assume, as we are perfectly entitled to do for the sake of argument, that life has originated only once in the universe, it follows that we are
allowed
to postulate a very large amount of luck in a theory, because there are so many planets in the universe where life
could
have originated. If, as one estimate has it, there are 100 billion billion planets, this is 100 billion times greater than even the very low SGP that we postulated. To conclude this argument, the maximum amount of luck that we are allowed to assume, before we reject a particular theory of the origin of life, has odds of one in
N
, where
N is
the number of suitable planets in the universe. There is a lot hidden in that word ‘suitable’, but let us put an upper limit of 1 in 100 billion billion for the maximum amount of luck that this argument entitles us to assume.

Think about what this means. We go to a chemist and say: get out your textbooks and your calculating machine; sharpen your pencil and your wits; fill your head with formulae, and your flasks with methane and ammonia and hydrogen and carbon dioxide and all the other gases that a primeval nonliving planet can be expected to have; cook them all up together; pass strokes of lightning through your simulated atmospheres, and strokes of inspiration through your brain; bring all your clever chemist’s methods to bear, and give us your best chemist’s estimate of the probability that a typical planet will spontaneously generate a selfreplicating molecule. Or, to put it another way, how long would we have to wait before random chemical events on the planet, random thermal jostling of atoms and molecules, resulted in a selfreplicating molecule?

Chemists don’t know the answer to this question. Most modern chemists would probably say that we’d have to wait a long time by the standards of a human lifetime, but perhaps not all that long by the standards of cosmological time. The fossil history of earth suggests that we have about a billion years - one ‘aeon’, to use a convenient modern definition - to play with, for this is roughly the time that elapsed between the origin of the Earth about 4.5 billion years ago and the era of the first fossil organisms. But the point of our ‘numbers of planets’ argument is that, even if the chemist said that we’d have to wait for a ‘miracle’, have to wait a billion billion years - far longer than the universe has existed, we can still accept this verdict with equanimity. There are probably more than a billion billion available planets in the universe. If each of them lasts as long as Earth, that gives us about a billion billion billion planet-years to play with. That will do nicely! A miracle is translated into practical politics by a multiplication sum.

There is a concealed assumption in this argument. Well, actually there are lots, but there’s one in particular that I want to talk about. This is that, once .life (i.e. replicators and cumulative selection) originates at all, it always advances to the point where its creatures evolve enough intelligence to speculate about their origins. If this is not so, our estimate of the amount of luck that we are allowed to postulate must be reduced accordingly. To be more precise, the maximum odds against the origin of life on any one planet that our theories are allowed to postulate, is the number of available planets in the universe divided by the odds that life, once started, will evolve sufficient intelligence to speculate about its own origins.

It may seem a little strange that ‘sufficient intelligence to speculate about its own origins’ is a relevant variable. To understand why it is, consider an alternative assumption. Suppose that the origin of life was quite a probable event, but the subsequent evolution of intelligence was exceedingly improbable, demanding a huge stroke of luck. Suppose the origin of intelligence is so improbable that it has happened on only one planet in the universe, even though life has started on many planets. Then, since we know we are intelligent enough to discuss the question, we know that Earth must be that one planet. Now suppose that the origin of life,
and
the origin of intelligence given that life is there, are
both
highly improbable events. Then the probability of any one planet, such as Earth, enjoying both strokes of luck is the
product
of the two low probabilities, and this is a far smaller probability.

It is as though, in our theory of how we came to exist, we are allowed to postulate a certain ration of luck. This ration has, as its upper limit, the number of eligible planets in the universe. Given our ration of luck, we can then ‘spend’ it as a limited commodity over the course of our explanation of our own existence. If we use up almost all our ration of luck in our theory of how life gets started on a planet in the first place, then we are allowed to postulate very little more luck in subsequent parts of our theory, in, say, the cumulative evolution of brains and intelligence. If we don’t use up all our ration of luck in our theory of the origin of life, we have some left over to spend on our theories of subsequent evolution, after cumulative selection has got going. If we want to use up most of our ration of luck in our theory of the origin of intelligence, then we haven’t much left over to spend on our theory of the origin of life: we must come up with a theory that makes the origin of life almost inevitable. Alternatively, if we don’t need our whole luck ration for these two stages of our theory, we can, in effect, use the surplus to postulate life elsewhere in the universe.

My personal feeling is that, once cumulative selection has got itself properly started, we need to postulate only a relatively small amount of luck in the subsequent evolution of life and intelligence. Cumulative selection, once it has begun, seems to me powerful enough to make the evolution of intelligence probable, if not inevitable. This means that we can, if we want to, spend virtually our entire ration of postulatable luck in one big throw, in our theory of the origin of life on a planet. Therefore we have at our disposal, if we want to use it, odds of 1 in 100 billion billion as an upper limit (or 1 in however many available planets we think there are) to spend in our theory of the origin of life. This is the maximum amount of luck we are allowed to postulate in our theory. Suppose we want to suggest, for instance, that life began when both DNA and its protein-based replication machinery spontaneously chanced to come into existence. We can allow ourselves the luxury of such an extravagant theory, provided that the odds against this coincidence occurring on a planet do not exceed 100 billion billion to one.

This allowance may seem large. It is probably ample to accommodate the spontaneous arising of DNA or RNA. But it is nowhere near enough to enable us to do without cumulative selection altogether. The odds against assembling a well-designed body that flies as well as a swift, or swims as well as a dolphin, or sees as well as a falcon, in a single blow of luck - single-step selection - are stupendously greater than the number of atoms in the universe, let alone the number of planets! No, it is certain that we are going to need a hefty measure of cumulative selection in our explanations of life.

But although we are entitled, in our theory of the origin of life, to spend a maximum ration of luck amounting, perhaps, to odds of 100 billion billion to one against, my hunch is that we aren’t going to need more than a small fraction of that ration. The origin of life on a planet can be a very improbable event indeed by our everyday standards, or indeed by the standards of the chemistry laboratory, and still be sufficiently probable to have occurred, not just once but many times, all over the universe. We can regard the statistical argument about numbers of planets as an argument of last resort. At the end of the chapter I shall make the paradoxical point that the theory we are looking for may actually
need to
seem improbable, even miraculous, to our subjective judgement (because of the way our subjective judgement has been made). Nevertheless, it is still sensible for us to begin by seeking that theory of the origin of life with the least degree of improbability. If the theory that DNA and its copying machinery arose spontaneously is so improbable that it obliges us to assume that life is very rare in the universe, and may even be unique to Earth, our’first resort is to try to find a more probable theory. So, can we come up with any speculations about relatively
probable
ways in which cumulative selection might have got its start?

The word ‘speculate’ has pejorative overtones, but these are quite uncalled for here. We can hope for nothing more than speculation when the events we are talking about took place four billion years ago and took place, moreover, in a world that must have been radically different from that which we know today. For instance, there almost certainly was no free oxygen in the atmosphere. Though the chemistry of the world may have changed, the
laws
of chemistry have not changed (that’s why they are called laws), and modern chemists know enough about those laws to make some well-informed speculations, speculations that have to pass rigorous tests of plausibility imposed by the laws. You can’t just speculate wildly and irresponsibly, allowing your imagination to run riot in the manner of such unsatisfying space fiction panaceas as ‘hyperdrives’, ‘time warps’ and ‘infinite improbability drives’. Of all possible speculations about the origin of life, most run foul of the laws of chemistry and can be ruled out, even if we make full use of our statistical fall-back argument about numbers of planets. Careful selective speculation is therefore a constructive exercise. But you do have to be a chemist to do it.

I am a biologist not a chemist, and I must rely on chemists to get their sums right. Different chemists prefer different pet theories, and there is no shortage of theories. I could attempt to lay all these theories before you impartially. That would be the proper thing to do in a student textbook. This isn’t a student textbook. The basic idea of
The Blind Watchmaker
is that we don’t need to postulate a designer in order to understand life, or anything else in the universe. We are here concerned with the
kind
of solution that must be found, because of the kind of problem we are faced with. I think that this is best explained, not by looking at lots of particular theories, but by looking at one as an example of how the basic problem - how cumulative selection got its Start -
might
be solved.

Now, which theory to choose as my representative sample? Most textbooks give greatest weight to the family of theories based on an organic ‘primeval soup’. It seems probable that the atmosphere of Earth before the coming of life was like that of other planets which are still lifeless. There was no oxygen, plenty of hydrogen and water, carbon dioxide, very likely some ammonia, methane and other simple organic gases. Chemists know that oxygen-free climates like this tend to foster the spontaneous synthesis of organic compounds. They have set up in flasks miniature reconstructions of conditions on the early Earth. They have passed through the flasks electric sparks simulating lightning, and ultraviolet light, which would have been much stronger before the Earth had an ozone layer shielding it from the sun’s rays. The results of these experiments have been exciting. Organic molecules, some of them of the same general types as are normally only found in living things, have spontaneously assembled themselves in these flasks. Neither DNA nor RNA has appeared, but the building blocks of these large molecules, called purines and pyrimidines, have. So have the building blocks of proteins, amino acids. The missing link for this class of theories is still the origin of replication. The building blocks haven’t come together to form a selfreplicating chain like RNA. Maybe one day they will.

Other books

Figgs & Phantoms by Ellen Raskin
Born of Stone by Missy Jane
Rush by Daniel Mason
The Orphans' Promise by Pierre Grimbert
Video Kill by Joanne Fluke
Outlaw Rose by Celeste Rupert
Loki's Game by Siobhan Kinkade
The Murder Stone by Louise Penny
Beyond the Sea by Keira Andrews
Arc D'X by Steve Erickson