Superintelligence: Paths, Dangers, Strategies (63 page)

Read Superintelligence: Paths, Dangers, Strategies Online

Authors: Nick Bostrom

Tags: #Science, #Philosophy, #Non-Fiction

BOOK: Superintelligence: Paths, Dangers, Strategies
11.87Mb size Format: txt, pdf, ePub

6
.
Pinker (2011); Wright (2001).

7
. It might be tempting to suppose the hypothesis that everything has accelerated to be meaningless on grounds that it does not (at first glance) seem to have any observational consequences; but see, e.g., Shoemaker (1969).

8
. The level of preparedness is not measured by the amount of effort expended on preparedness activities, but by how propitiously configured conditions actually are and how well-poised key decision makers are to take appropriate action.

9
. The degree of international trust during the lead-up to the intelligence explosion may also be a factor. We consider this in the section “Collaboration” later in the chapter.

10
. Anecdotally, it appears those currently seriously interested in the control problem are disproportionately sampled from one extreme end of the intelligence distribution, though there could be alternative explanations for this impression. If the field becomes fashionable, it will undoubtedly be flooded with mediocrities and cranks.

11
. I owe this term to Carl Shulman.

12
. How similar to a brain does a machine intelligence have to be to count as a whole brain emulation rather than a neuromorphic AI? The relevant determinant might be whether the system reproduces either the values or the full panoply of cognitive and evaluative tendencies of either a particular individual or a generic human being, because this would plausibly make a difference to the control problem. Capturing these properties may require a rather high degree of emulation fidelity.

13
. The magnitude of the boost would of course depend on how big the push was, and also where resources for the push came from. There might be no net boost for neuroscience if all the extra resources invested in whole brain emulation research were deducted from regular neuroscience research—unless a keener focus on emulation research just happened to be a more effective way of advancing neuroscience than the default portfolio of neuroscience research.

14
. See Drexler (1986, 242). Drexler (private communication) confirms that this reconstruction corresponds to the reasoning he was seeking to present. Obviously, a number of implicit premisses would have to be added if one wished to cast the argument in the form of a deductively valid chain of reasoning.

15
. Perhaps we ought not to welcome
small
catastrophes in case they increase our vigilance to the point of making us prevent the
medium-scale
catastrophes that would have been needed to make us take the strong precautions necessary to prevent existential catastrophes? (And of course, just as with biological immune systems, we also need to be concerned with over-reactions, analogous to allergies and autoimmune disorders.)

16
. Cf. Lenman (2000); Burch-Brown (2014).

17
. Cf. Bostrom (2007).

18
. Note that this argument focuses on the ordering rather than the timing of the relevant events. Making superintelligence happen earlier would help preempt other existential transition risks only if the intervention changes the sequence of the key developments: for example, by making superintelligence happen before various milestones are reached in nanotechnology or synthetic biology.

19
. If solving the control problem is
extremely
difficult compared to solving the performance problem in machine intelligence, and if project ability correlates only weakly with project size, then it is possible that it would be better that a small project gets there first, namely if the variance in capability is greater among smaller projects. In such a situation, even if smaller projects are on average less competent than larger projects, it could be less unlikely that a given small project would happen to have the freakishly high level of competence needed to solve the control problem.

20
. This is not to deny that one can imagine tools that could promote global deliberation and which would benefit from, or even require, further progress in hardware—for example, high-quality translation, better search, ubiquitous access to smart phones, attractive virtual reality environments for social intercourse, and so forth.

21
. Investment in emulation technology could speed progress toward whole brain emulation not only directly (through any technical deliverables produced) but also indirectly by creating a
constituency that will push for more funding and boost the visibility and credibility of the whole brain emulation (WBE) vision.

22
. How much expected value would be lost if the future were shaped by the desires of one random human rather than by (some suitable superposition of) the desires of all of humanity? This might depend sensitively on what evaluation standard we use, and also on whether the desires in question are idealized or raw.

23
. For example, whereas human minds communicate slowly via language, AIs can be designed so that instances of the same program are able easily and quickly to transfer both skills and information amongst one another. Machine minds designed
ab initio
could do away with cumbersome legacy systems that helped our ancestors deal with aspects of the natural environment that are unimportant in cyberspace. Digital minds might also be designed to take advantage of fast serial processing unavailable to biological brains, and to make it easy to install new modules with highly optimized functionality (e.g. symbolic processing, pattern recognition, simulators, data mining, and planning). Artificial intelligence might also have significant non-technical advantages, such as being more easily patentable or less entangled in the moral complexities of using human uploads.

24
. If
p
1
and
p
2
are the probabilities of failure at each step, the total probability of failure is
p
1
+ (1 –
p
1
)
p
2
since one can fail terminally only once.

25
. It is possible, of course, that the frontrunner will not have such a large lead and will not be able to form a singleton. It is also possible that a singleton would arise before AI even without the intervention of WBE, in which case this reason for favoring a WBE-first scenario falls away.

26
. Is there a way for a promoter of WBE to increase the specificity of her support so that it accelerates WBE while minimizing the spillover to AI development? Promoting scanning technology is probably a better bet than promoting neurocomputational modeling. (Promoting computer hardware is unlikely to make much difference one way or the other, given the large commercial interests that are anyway incentivizing progress in that field.)

Promoting scanning technology may increase the likelihood of a multipolar outcome by making scanning less likely to be a bottleneck, thus increasing the chance that the early emulation population will be stamped from many different human templates rather than consisting of gazillions of copies of a tiny number of templates. Progress in scanning technology also makes it more likely that the bottleneck will instead be computing hardware, which would tend to slow the takeoff.

27
. Neuromorphic AI may also lack other safety-promoting attributes of whole brain emulation, such as having a profile of cognitive strengths and weaknesses similar to that of a biological human being (which would let us use our experience of humans to form some expectations of the system’s capabilities at different stages of its development).

28
. If somebody’s motive for promoting WBE is to make WBE happen before AI, they should bear in mind that accelerating WBE will alter the order of arrival only if the default timing of the two paths toward machine intelligence is close and with a slight edge to AI. Otherwise,
either
investment in WBE will simply make WBE happen earlier than it otherwise would (reducing hardware overhang and preparation time) but without affecting the sequence of development;
or else
such investment in WBE will have little effect (other than perhaps making AI happen even sooner by stimulating progress on neuromorphic AI).

29
. Comment on Hanson (2009).

30
. There would of course be
some
magnitude and imminence of existential risk for which it would be preferable even from the person-affecting perspective to postpone the risk—whether to enable existing people to eke out a bit more life before the curtain drops or to provide more time for mitigation efforts that might reduce the danger.

31
. Suppose we could take some action that would bring the intelligence explosion closer by one year. Let us say that the people currently inhabiting the Earth are dying off at a rate of 1% per year, and that the default risk of human extinction from the intelligence explosion is 20% (to pick an arbitrary number for the purposes of illustration only). Then hastening the arrival of the intelligence explosion by 1 year might be worth (from a person-affecting standpoint) an increase in the risk from 20% to 21%, i.e. a 5% increase in risk level. However, the vast majority
of people alive one year before the start of the intelligence explosion would at that point have an interest in postponing it if they could thereby reduce the risk of the explosion by one percentage point (since most individuals would reckon their own risk of dying in the next year to be much smaller than 1%—given that most mortality occurs in relatively narrow demographics such as the frail and the elderly). One could thus have a model in which each year the population votes to postpone the intelligence explosion by another year, so that the intelligence explosion never happens, although everybody who ever lives agrees that it would be better if the intelligence explosion happened at some point. In reality, of course, coordination failures, limited predictability, or preferences for things other than personal survival are likely to prevent such an unending pause.

If one uses the standard economic discount factor instead of the person-affecting standard, the magnitude of the potential upside is diminished, since the value of existing people getting to enjoy astronomically long lives is then steeply discounted. This effect is especially strong if the discount factor is applied to each individual’s subjective time rather than to sidereal time. If future benefits are discounted at a rate of
x
% per year, and the background level of existential risk from other sources is
y
% per year, then the optimum point for the intelligence explosion would be when delaying the explosion for another year would produce less than
x
+
y
percentage points of reduction of the existential risk associated with an intelligence explosion.

32
. I am indebted to Carl Shulman and Stuart Armstrong for help with this model. See also Shulman (2010a, 3): “Chalmers (2010) reports a consensus among cadets and staff at the U.S. West Point military academy that the U.S. government would not restrain AI research even in the face of potential catastrophe, for fear that rival powers would gain decisive advantage.”

33
. That is, information in the model is always bad
ex ante
. Of course, depending on what the information actually is, it will in some cases turn out to be good that the information became known, notably if the gap between leader and runner-up is much greater than one would reasonably have guessed in advance.

34
. It might even present an existential risk, especially if preceded by the introduction of novel military technologies of destruction or unprecedented arms buildups.

35
. A project could have its workers distributed over a large number of locations and collaborating via encrypted communications channels. But this tactic involves a security trade-off: while geographical dispersion may offer some protection against military attacks, it would impede operational security, since it is harder to prevent personnel from defecting, leaking information, or being abducted by a rival power if they are spread out over many locations.

36
. Note that a large temporal discount factor could make a project behave in some ways as though it were in a race, even if it knows it has no real competitor. The large discount factor means it would care little about the far future. Depending on the situation, this would discourage blue-sky R&D, which would tend to delay the machine intelligence revolution (though perhaps making it more abrupt when it does occur, because of hardware overhang). But the large discount factor—or a low level of caring for future generations—would also make existential risks seem to matter less. This would encourage gambles that involve the possibility of an immediate gain at the expense of an increased risk of existential catastrophe, thus disincentivizing safety investment and incentivizing an early launch—mimicking the effects of the race dynamic. By contrast to the race dynamic, however, a large discount factor (or disregard for future generations) would have no particular tendency to incite conflict.

Reducing the race dynamic is a main benefit of collaboration. That collaboration would facilitate sharing of ideas for how to solve the control problem is also a benefit, although this is to some extent counterbalanced by the fact that collaboration would also facilitate sharing of ideas for how to solve the competence problem. The net effect of this facilitation of idea-sharing may be to slightly increase the collective intelligence of the relevant research community.

Other books

Mother's Day by Lynne Constantine
Takeover by Viguerie, Richard A.
Ms. Coco Is Loco! by Dan Gutman
The English Girl by Margaret Leroy
Sarah Gabriel by Stealing Sophie
An Arm and a Leg by Olive Balla
Phoenix Heart by Nash, Carolyn
Finally His by Emma Hillman
Avalanche by Tallulah Grace
La Maldición del Maestro by Laura Gallego García