First Among Equals (4 page)

Read First Among Equals Online

Authors: Kenneth W. Starr

Tags: #CUR005000

BOOK: First Among Equals
11.93Mb size Format: txt, pdf, ePub

Like Hamilton, Jefferson also served in Washington's cabinet. He was the loser in these early battles. His vision of a federal government strictly confined to the powers enumerated in the Constitution had failed to carry the day during Washington's two terms. Jefferson then lost a hard-fought, bitter contest to John Adams in 1796. But Jefferson was tenacious, determined to best the centralizing forces of the Federalist Party epitomized by his adversary, now President Adams. In 1800, his defeat of Adams, a virtuous, principled man lacking in political skills, finally brought the states’ rights advocates—the so-called Anti-Federalists—to power. The “Revolution of 1800,” as Jefferson dubbed the election, occurred after twelve successive years of Federalist domination.

The business of the Supreme Court now began to pick up. Not only was there more work to do at the Court itself, but the justices often found themselves “riding circuit.” They would literally ride on horseback or take coaches to various cities and preside at trials.

Not surprisingly, the Court, stocked as it was with Washington's and then Adams's appointees, was strongly pro-Federalist. Chief Justice Oliver Ellsworth's resignation in late 1800 gave the Federalists the opportunity to deepen their influence upon the judiciary. Notwithstanding his lame-duck status, President Adams took advantage of the Ellsworth resignation and nominated a brilliant, loyal Federalist from Virginia, John Marshall, to become chief justice. Adams also rushed through nominations of other judges to the lower courts. The “midnight appointees,” as they came to be known, were destined to dominate the federal courts for years to come. But no other appointment in history had the enduring impact of John Marshall's.

More than any other figure save for Washington himself, John Marshall gave shape to the national government. In particular, Marshall affirmed the power of the nation's highest court to interpret the Constitution and federal law. Known as the power of judicial review, it was first given full expression in the 1803 case of
Marbury v. Madison.
The underlying dispute was simple: Was William Marbury entitled to a commission that, upon delivery, would permit him to take the oath of office as a justice of the peace in the new District of Columbia? From that tiny legal dispute a mighty doctrine grew.

The issue is this: In a constitutional democracy, the Constitution is the ultimate authority, binding on all branches and levels of government. But the Constitution, since it is a written document, must be interpreted. Who is to do that? May each branch of government interpret the Constitution for itself? What if the president or Congress reads the Constitution differently from the Supreme Court? Which branch prevails?

In the case that resolved this issue, William Marbury invoked a measure passed by Congress and signed into law by George Washington. The statute was the Judiciary Act of 1789. That law, among other things, created the attorney general's office. It created the United States Marshals. It created lower federal courts.

But another provision of that law—and one invoked by would-be Justice of the Peace Marbury—said that the Supreme Court could hear as an “original” matter (that is, without any lower court passing on the case) certain legal actions, namely lawsuits seeking a writ of mandamus. Mandamus is an ancient writ at common law and is still in active use today. To “mandamus” someone is to secure an extraordinary directive requiring an official (including judges) to take certain action, or to cease and desist from a court taking certain action (called in bygone years a writ of prohibition).

Invoking the mandamus provision, William Marbury filed a petition in the Supreme Court to mandamus the incoming secretary of state, James Madison, to deliver the justice-of-the-peace commission that had been authorized by outgoing President John Adams and signed by then Secretary of State John Marshall. Marshall, who hadn't delivered Marbury his commission, was now chief justice.

Marbury doubtless entered the High Court brimming with optimism. This was, after all, a Federalist bench from top to bottom. These were the appointees of Washington and Adams. The commission was surely his.

There was a huge problem, however, one unanticipated by Marbury's argument. The issue had to do with the Supreme Court's authority to hear the case, what lawyers and judges call “jurisdiction.” Jurisdiction is a fundamental issue for courts. Judges routinely ask: Do we have power—i.e., jurisdiction—to hear this lawsuit? Are the litigants in the right court? Does this plaintiff have “standing” (some legally recognizable injury) to mount the legal challenge in question? Is there a statute, passed in accordance with the Constitution, conferring power on the courts to resolve the particular case?

In particular, federal courts (including the Supreme Court) worry about their authority in a federal system: “Counsel, what right does your client have to be here?” The basic point is this: In our system of government, courts are limited in their authority. Although within their sphere of authority they are powerful indeed, courts can do only what the law creating them authorizes. To go beyond that power is to behave lawlessly.

Occasionally, judges will be insufficiently attentive to what they consider jurisdictional niceties. An episode during my service in the 1980s as a judge on the U.S. Court of Appeals in Washington, D.C., illustrates the point. One of the giants of the district court in Washington at the time was Gerhard Gesell, son of the renowned Yale child psychologist and a distinguished lawyer in his own right at Washington's prestigious Covington & Burling. Before his appointment to the bench, Gesell had been one of the nation's premier antitrust advocates. He was smart and shrewd. Each year, he would sit by designation for several days as a guest judge on the court of appeals in Washington. On one such occasion, as we were chatting in the judges’ robing room just behind the courtroom, Gesell was complaining about recent opinions from our court tightening up the rules of standing, saying, “Let's get on with these cases, get to the merits, instead of wrestling with all this technical stuff.” Gesell was a bit testy on the point. He seldom hesitated to speak his mind, but he seemed especially agitated over this trend toward “technical” decisions. I was amused, but listened politely. I liked Gerry a lot, and respected his opinions. The presiding judge that morning was Robert Bork. Always quick, Judge Bork reminded the venerable district judge that these recent opinions didn't simply reflect some hypertechnical approach: “Well, Gerry, it is constitutionally required, you know.” What Judge Bork was saying is this: Courts are limited, by Article III of the Constitution, to deciding actual cases and controversies. Gesell snorted. Here was the practical, common-sense district judge who wanted to move the cases along and get them decided, on the one hand, pitted against the principle, rooted in the idea of a limited judiciary, that judges can't decide anything and everything parties might choose to bring them.

This was the problem that confronted Marbury. He had brought his case to the Supreme Court instead of some lower court because the Judiciary Act of 1789 told him he could. But this, Chief Justice Marshall concluded, was impermissible. The text of the Constitution itself—in Article III setting forth the judicial power and creating the Supreme Court—designated the specific categories of cases in which the Supreme Court enjoyed “original” (that is, firsthand) jurisdiction. What Marbury was seeking— mandamus—was not within those categories.

Thus, the 1789 statute tried to expand what the Constitution itself established. The categories of original jurisdiction created by the Constitution were closed (barring, of course, a constitutional amendment). Congress could not depart from the text of Article III and devise additional categories of original jurisdiction. Obviously, the statute was inconsistent with what the Constitution provided. Both could not be law.

The final step in John Marshall's analysis represented the inexorable conclusion: If a statute passed by Congress is inconsistent with the Constitution, then the statute must be set aside. Otherwise, ordinary legislation would render ineffectual the very law that sets up Congress and the rest of the government—the Constitution. And, Marshall added, it was the job of judges to say, finally, what was the law of the land.

The Federalist midnight appointee John Marshall had ruled against his philosophical comrade. But in the process of disappointing Marbury, the great chief justice (as he came to be called) had established the fundamental role of the judiciary in a constitutional democracy—to interpret the Constitution finally and authoritatively, even when one of the other branches of government (or both) had come to a contrary view.

To Jefferson, the
Marbury v. Madison
approach was profoundly wrong. Each branch, he thought, was coordinate and co-equal. It would not do to have a regime of judicial supremacy in which the unelected, third branch of government stood over the two elected branches. A new aristocracy would rule the two branches most responsive to the people.

But President Jefferson's sense of foreboding was to no avail. Congress made no effort to overturn
Marbury
through constitutional amendment. Nor was a more modest measure seriously pursued, such as one requiring that the Court be unanimous before striking down as unconstitutional an act of Congress or an action of the executive branch.

Marbury v. Madison
was the seminal decision of John Marshall's tenure. But it began a long series of Marshall's contributions. In case after case, spanning over three decades of service, Marshall guided the Court in a way that upheld national power over the country. That is, when the issue involved the power of the Congress as against the claims of the states, Marshall was a reliable supporter of the federal government. In particular, his interpretation of one pivotal provision in the Constitution — the Commerce Clause—paved the way for Congress to be free to regulate the economy in the myriad ways that have now become commonplace.

Much of what Congress does falls under the category of regulating “commerce.” The Constitution's language in this respect is simple: Article I, section 8 provides that the national legislature is empowered “[t]o regulate Commerce with foreign Nations, and among the several states, and with the Indian Tribes.” In an early landmark testing the extent of this power, Marshall, in a characteristically broad interpretation of congressional authority, dealt a serious blow to state authority (
Gibbons v. Ogden
[1824]). In that case, the Marshall Court struck down a New York law giving a monopoly to a steamboat company carrying passengers on the Hudson River. In overturning the law, Marshall gave the pivotal term
commerce
a sweepingly broad definition, thus maximizing federal power at the expense of the states.

Marshall's pro-Federalist vision likewise triumphed in an early case involving Maryland's challenge to the controversial remnant of Hamilton's program from the prior century, the Bank of the United States. To the Anti-Federalist defenders of states’ rights, most prominently Jefferson, the Bank embodied the evils of national concentration of power. Nowhere in the Constitution was the Bank either generally or specifically mentioned. The legality of the Bank thus went to the heart of the Constitution's structural arrangements. The Constitution, after all, laid out in elaborate detail the various powers of Congress. To the Anti-Federalists, its silence about national financial institutions resolved the question of Congress's power: If the Constitution was silent, then the power did not exist.

This narrow approach to interpreting the Constitution is frequently referred to as “strict construction.” A strict constructionist, as the term is generally used, is a judge or justice who discerns the meaning of the Constitution in its text, structure, and history. Many nominees for judicial office will march under the banner of strict construction, since it suggests a modest, limited role for judges in a democratic society. Judges, advocates of strict construction say, should not import their own views of good and sound policy into the clauses and phrases of the supreme law of the land.

Despite its popular appeal, strict construction has only episodically characterized the Supreme Court's work. The enduring approach toward constitutional interpretation was outlined by John Marshall in the landmark decision involving the Bank of the United States. The case was
McCulloch v. Maryland,
decided in 1819. Showing its hostility toward the national bank, Maryland imposed a tax on all banks or branches operating in the state that had not been chartered by the state legislature in Annapolis. The cashier of the Baltimore branch of the national bank, James McCulloch, issued notes on which no state tax had been paid, and the Maryland authorities filed an action in state court to collect the taxes due. The state courts ruled in favor of Maryland, and the case found its way to the Marshall Court.

The Court, speaking through Marshall, invoked a provision in the Constitution that Maryland had largely ignored. The “Necessary and Proper” Clause—the final clause of Article I, section 8—provided that Congress was empowered “to make all Laws which shall be necessary and proper for carrying into Execution the foregoing Powers,” which were specifically listed. In broad language that has stood the test of time, Marshall wrote that the “Necessary and Proper” Clause gives great latitude to Congress in working its will. “Let the end be legitimate,” wrote Marshall, “let it be within the scope of the Constitution, and all means which are appropriate, which are plainly adapted to that end, which are not prohibited, but consistent with the letter and spirit of the Constitution, are constitutional.” This was an open-ended approach that would allow Congress and the president to work their will on the nation. Hamilton's dream would live on.

More important for the future, John Marshall's approach to interpreting the Constitution would stand as one of the great legacies of his tenure. The Constitution was to be interpreted broadly, not narrowly. In Marshall's approach, the Constitution was quite different from ordinary law. In criminal law, for example, one of the rules of interpretation is that criminal statutes should be construed narrowly. The “rule of lenity” puts a thumb on the scales in favor of individual liberty. An individual should not, under our system of law, be charged with a crime unless the nature of the criminal offense is clear to an ordinary person. Ambiguity or uncertainty in the criminal law is to be interpreted against the government and in favor of the individual. The opposite approach applies, however, when the Constitution, rather than a criminal statute, is being interpreted. As Chief Justice Marshall put it, “We must never forget that it is a Constitution that we are expounding.” The Constitution, in short, must be interpreted in a generous, reasonable manner, with the judge aware that the Constitution was intended to set forth a workable, practical structure of government. The frame of mind of the interpreting justice, in this view, is one of flexibility and practicality, with the operations of government clearly in mind.

Other books

Tudor by Leanda de Lisle
Men in Green Faces by Gene Wentz, B. Abell Jurus
Prison Ship by Bowers, Michael
Winter Warriors by David Gemmell
The Dead Hand of History by Sally Spencer