The Outsider (27 page)

Read The Outsider Online

Authors: Colin Wilson

BOOK: The Outsider
3.38Mb size Format: txt, pdf, ePub

But Nietzsche considered that his perception clashed with the Christian idea, that the body is the

frail and unimportant tenement of the soul
5
. The doctrine of introversion that underlay most ascetic Christianity in the Middle Ages (and still governs a great deal of monastic life) holds that Man originally was completely free; the Fall made him a slave of outward things; his salvation, therefore, lies in turning the attention inward, away from outside things. Blake, who was always more interested in Christ than in historic Christianity, found no body-contempt in Christ and could therefore declare himself a Christian without misgivings; Nietzsche was always more aware of Luther than Christ; Luther undoubtedly
was
a contemner of the body; Nietzsche called
v
himself an Anti-Christ when he more probably meant an Anti-Luther. Nietzsche

s temperament was less devotional, more intellectual, than Blake

s; there is a fundamental similarity all the same, and it would be more accurate to regard Nietzsche as a Blakeian Christian than as an irreligious pagan. Always provided, of course, we know what we mean by a Blakeian Christian (unfortunately, it is beyond the scope of this book to study Blake

s conception of Christianity).

Nietzsche understood the Outsider far better than anyone we have spoken of so far. Lawrence and Van Gogh were men working in the dark; Nietzsche wasn

t.

Not the height, but the drop, is terrible. That precipice in which the glance falls down while the hand gropes up.
...

My Will clings to man; with chains I bind myself to man,
because I am drawn upwards towards the Superman; thither tends my
other
Will.
32

For Nietzsche had taken the next great step; he had escaped from Evan Strowde

s world without motive; he had grasped with both hands his destiny as a prophet. He grasped it, even though it meant standing completely alone. At first he believed it was a

will to truth at all costs

that drove him. Later he plumbed his purpose to its depths; not simply a will to truth— that is not enough—but a will to life, to consciousness, to infusion of spirit into dead matter.

That was not the end of the problem. It might have been, if our civilization were two thousand years younger. What Nietzsche wanted to do was to start a new religion. Like Rilke

s Malte, he felt that he was the only man who realized the necessity, and consequently that he alone should begin the tremendous work. But he wasn

t sure how to begin. He had been trained as a philologist. He might have been better off if he had been trained as a priest or a novelist. Newman, for instance, was fundamentally very like Nietzsche, and he was lucky enough to find his way into an existing institution;
that
was the sensible thing to do, since retiring into the wilderness is not a practical expedient for a modern European. At the same time, we must admit that Nietzsche

s influence has been far greater than Newman

s, simply because Newman
did
choose to express himself inside the Church. Nietzsche

s heroism is relatively greater; his suffering was greater; his tragedy affects us as Newman

s obscurer tragedy does not.

Yet the really terrible element in Nietzsche

s life is the
waste.
Under the right circumstances, Nietzsche would have had the strength to bring about a spiritual revival; instead he died insane, like a big gun with some trifling mechanical fault that explodes and kills all the crew. With all the power in his hands, with a psychological insight into himself that makes even Lawrence seem by comparison an amateur in introspection, Nietzsche cracked up. Why did he crack up? How could he have avoided it? Something was wrong. The new religion was never born. Nietzsche was misunderstood, more by the neurotics who claimed to be Nietzscheans than by his enemies. It is an immense problem. Since Nietzsche

s death, two major prophets of Nietzschean rank have attacked it again: Shaw and Gurdjieff
(I shall glance briefly at their contributions to the Outsider

s solution, in the last chapter of this book). Neither can be said to have solved it, although both have taken it on to new ground, and achieved some intellectually exciting results. Mr. Eliot has solved it for himself by his

back to tradition

doctrine. This is also an aspect that will be easier to approach when we speak of T. E. Hulme in the last chapter.

At this point, we can summarize Nietzsche

s contribution. He has solved the body-emotions-intellect equation, and arrived at the same conclusion we arrived at in Chapter IV. He has shown that he feels the Outsider to be a prophet in disguise-disguised even from himself—whose salvation lies in discovering his deepest purpose, and then throwing himself into it. He has no tendency towards a Sartre doctrine of commitment —that any purpose will do provided it is altruistic. If we tried to express the prophet

s purpose in its simplest graspable form, we could say that it was a desire to shout

Wake up!

in everybody

s ear. But wake up to what? Wake up from what? Are all men asleep then?

Obviously, what we lack now is a penetrating psychological estimate of the human situation. All this has only a limited meaning until we can say: This is what man is, this is what he is intended to do.

In this chapter, I have not tried to survey the full extent of Nietzsche

s attempted answer to these questions; I have not even quoted the books in which he deals most seriously with Outsider problems
(Beyond Good and Evil, The Genealogy of Morals, The Will to Power).
To a certain extent, the next two chapters will make this superfluous. Besides, it is not a philosopher

s problem; Nietzsche himself discovered: Intellect is not enough. Yet he remained a philosopher who continued to attack the problems with a philosopher

s tools: the language of criticism, the ordering of thoughts into paragraphs and chapters. But Zarathustra made it clear in which direction the answer lay; it is towards the artist-psychologist, the intuitional thinker. There are very few such men in the world

s literature; the great artists are not thinkers, the great thinkers are seldom artists. One of the few nations that have produced great men who combined the two faculties is Russia; and it is to Russia

s two greatest novelists that we must turn now for further treatment of the Outsider.

 

 

 

 

CHAPTER SIX

 

THE QUESTION OF IDENTITY

 

The outsider
is
not
sure who he is.

He has found an

I

, but it is not his true

I

.

His main business is to find his way back to himself.

This is not so easy. In fact, strictly speaking, we have not touched on the problem yet. We have only analysed the Outsider

s

lostness

. Even

the attempt to gain control

was a failure that only provided more insight into the Outsider

s complicated clockwork. To find a way back to himself: that is how we have provisionally defined his aim. But it is not a simple affair, as certain successful modern novelists have made it appear in their fictionalized treatment of Outsiders (

bestsellers

about the life of Van Gogh, Gauguin, etc.). It calls for detailed psychological analysis; for an exactitude of language for which there is no precedent in modern literature (if we except the poetry of Mr. Eliot, especially the Tour Quartets

, and certain passages in Joyce

s
Ulysses).
It is a subject which is full of pitfalls for the understanding. And writing about it drives home the fact that our language has become a tired and inefficient thing in the hands of journalists and writers who have nothing to say.

Now language is the natural medium for self-analysis; the idea of

a way back to himself cannot be expressed in any other medium. But it cannot have escaped the reader

s attention that all our analysis so far has aimed at defining what the Outsider means by

himself, and that we have barely touched on the question of

the way\
To a certain degree, of course, one question follows another, but the point I wish to make here is the fact that the

way

is not a matter for
words,
but a matter for action. At a certain point, the Outsider asks Bunyan

s question,

What must I
do
to be saved?

If his answer is Evan Strowde

s:

Nothing is worth doing

, then there is no help for it, he had better cut his throat or commit mind-suicide. Fortunately, Strowde

s answer is not a logical bottleneck; we can still attack the question from another angle and ask: saved from
what?
And this reduces the problem to a more graspable form; in
fact to our Ultimate Yes or Ultimate No. For

saved from what

immediately involves the further question: What is the
worst
you can be saved from? in short, what is the worst form of Ultimate No? We have mentioned some appalling examples: Hiroshima, the Armenian Massacre—and there are pages in
The Seven Pillars of Wisdom
that are terrible enough to put a sensitive person off his dinner. But after all, they are not ultimate forms of evil; they are old stuff, quite familiar in history. You can read several examples in the Assyrian Room at the British Museum: how Assur Nasir Pal II

burned their young men and maidens in a fire

and committed other cruelties that are too revolting to quote, but that, after all, can quite easily be paralleled by Belsen and Buchenwald after another three thousand years of civilization have elapsed. No, these evils are oppressive, but they do not hang over us with a sense of being inescapable.

It is when we consider the

vastations

of the Jameses, father and son, that we come closer to the problem of real evil. This evil comes nearer home;
it attacks the mind,
not the body. Assur Nasir Pal and the men he tortured to death could alike be reduced to

a quivering mass of fear

by it. Hitler would be as defenceless against it as the Jews of the Warsaw Ghetto. In such an appalling light, men are no longer real beings; they are reduced to a common level of unreality:

Think of us, not as lost, violent souls

But only as the hollow men, the stuffed men,

If the hour should strike for me as it struck for him,

nothing I possess could save me.
...

This is a terrible conclusion to accept. As human beings, we cannot accept it. We must repeat the question: Is there no way out?

* * *

 

Our method in approaching this problem must be the same as usual: to take concrete examples. Again, we might look to William James for a direction. Religious cases are

out

; this narrows the choice of

sick souls

. But among other cases, James quotes Tolstoy

s
Confession,
and this seems to be an excellent starting-point, for Tolstoy at least
began
as a free-thinker, after
the fashion of the 30

s of the last century. Moreover, Tolstoy resembles Nietzsche and Kierkegaard in that he reached religious conclusions while finding it impossible to support the orthodox Church—another feature common to Outsiders.

A Confession
tells how, in his fiftieth year, Tolstoy (by that time the famous author of
War and Peace
and
Anna Karenina)
began to be troubled by the questions:

What is life? Why should I live ? Why should I do anything? Is there any meaning in life that can overcome inevitable death?

It is interesting to note that Tolstoy says, and evidently believes, that these questions had never seriously troubled him before; in spite of which, fifteen years earlier, we have him putting into the mouth of Peter Bezhukov in
War and Peace
the words:

What is bad? What is good?
...
What does one live for? What am I ? What is life and What is death?

, etc.
1
There are obviously
degrees
of awareness of Outsider problems, and the force of the later occasion made Tolstoy dismiss the earlier. But we must also note the fact that, the harder the problems strike, the more they disable the man. Tolstoy is an example of the phenomenon I mentioned in Chapter IV, partial solution of the problems and partial remaining in the old, once-born state. Again, in
War and Peace
,
in the firing-squad scene, Peter observes that the soldiers
are not aware of the nature of what they are doing.
2
The problem of death, and of meaning in life, is completely dissociated from human cruelty and

man

s inhumanity to man

. Assur Nasir Pal and Hitler hardly enter into it. It is the observation of Walter Pater

s Florian
[
Child in the House
]
that all living creatures are involved in

a vast web of cruelty

, no matter how gentle and humane they may be. Evil is Outside.

Tolstoy

s experiences began like Roquentin

s:

Five years ago something very strange began to happen to me. At first I experienced moments of perplexity and arrest of life, as though I did not know how to five or what to do.
...
Then these moments of perplexity re
curred oftener and oftener…

3

Finally, attacks of

the nausea

.

I felt that what I had been standing on had broken down, and that I had nothing left under my feet. What I had lived on no longer existed, and I had nothing left to live on.

4

Other books

Moon-Flash by Patricia A. McKillip
The Waking Engine by David Edison
Merely Players by J M Gregson
Flash Point by Shelli Stevens
Vicious Circles by Leann Andrews
Pamela Dean by Tam Lin (pdf)
Beyond Seduction by Emma Holly