Read The State by Anthony de Jasay Online

Authors: Anthony de Jasay

Tags: #Politics

The State by Anthony de Jasay (27 page)

BOOK: The State by Anthony de Jasay
3.28Mb size Format: txt, pdf, ePub
ads

"prudent" and "conservative," myths of this type are liable to sway many minds for some time to come, albeit for reasons which Rawls would be the first to disavow.

 
  1. In his system, the characteristics of the "original position" (ignorance about one's vital particulars coupled with some selective general knowledge of economics and politics), and three psychological assumptions, together determine what people would decide if put in such a position. They will choose Rawls's second principle, notably the part of it enjoining the maximization of the minimum lot in an unknown distribution of lots, or "difference principle." (The case for saying that they will also choose the first principle concerning equal liberty, and bar any more-of-one for less-of-the-other type of compromise between liberty and other "primary goods," is much less open-and-shut, but we will not concern ourselves with that.) The first point at issue is whether the psychological assumptions leading to the maximin choice can properly be made about rational men in general, or whether they represent the special case histories of somewhat eccentric persons.
  2.  
  3. The end postulated for the rational man is the fulfilment of his life-plan. He ignores its particulars except that it takes a certain sufficiency of primary goods to fulfil it; these goods, then, serve needs and not desires.*37 However, it is hard to see what else makes a fulfilled life-plan into a worth-while end if it is not the expected enjoyment of the very primary goods which go into its fulfilment; they are the means but they must also be the ends.*38 The latter is really implied in their being goods whose index we seek to maximize (rather than merely bring to a level of adequacy) for the least-advantaged. Yet we are told that people are not anxious to have more of them once they have enough for fulfilling

the plan. They show no interest in its over-fulfilment! This position is ambiguous, if not downright obscure.

 
  1. To dispel the ambiguity, one could suppose that people want to fulfil the life-plan, not because of the lifelong access to enjoyable primary goods for which it is a shorthand symbol, but as an end in itself. The life-plan is like climbing Piz Palu which we just want to do, and primary goods are like climbing boots, of no value except as tools. The life-plan either succeeds, or it fails, with no half-way house. It is not a continuous variable, of which it is good to have a little and better to have a lot. It is an either/or matter; we do not want to climb Piz Palu a little, nor can we climb higher than its peak. The lack of interest in more than a sufficiency of primary goods would then make sense, too, for who wants two pairs of boots for climbing one mountain?
  2.  
  3. This logical consistency between the end and the means (a necessary condition of rationality) would, however, be bought at the price of imputing to rational men much the same absolute view of the life-plan that saints have of salvation. Damnation is unacceptable; salvation is exactly sufficient and nothing else matters besides; it is nonsense to want more salvation. The life-plan is an un-analysable whole. We do not and need not know what the good is of fulfilling it. However, it seems meaningless to wish to more-than-fulfil it, and utter hell to fall short.
  4.  
  5. There is nothing irrational per se in imputing an uncompromising, saintly mentality to people engaged in devising distributive institutions; saints can be as rational or as irrational as sinners. The problem is rather that, unlike salvation which has profound meaning and content for the believer, the life-plan is emptied of

content if it must be abstracted from command over primary goods (i.e. if the latter are to be stopped from serving as ends); can it still be sustained that it is the goal of the rational man to fulfil it, though it looks an unexplained eccentricity to want to do so? Besides this, it is hardly worth mentioning that interpreting the life-plan as an ultimate end, and an all-or-nothing affair at that, is forbidden by Rawls's own view that it is a mosaic of sub-plans which are fulfilled separately and perhaps also successively (see chapter VII), i.e. not an indivisible goal in which you either succeed or fail.

 

3.4.8
The significance of this question resides in the role three specific psychological assumptions are called upon to play in making rational people "choose maximin." Take the last two first. We are told (1) that "the person choosing... cares very little, if anything, for what he might gain above the minimum stipend" (p. 154), and

(2)
that he rejects alternative choices which involve someprobability, however minute, that he might get less than that, because "the rejected alternatives have outcomes that one can hardly accept" (p. 154). If these two assumptions were to be interpreted literally, the choosers would behave as if they had the single-point objective of climbing to a chosen mountain-top. They would go for a critical quantity (index number) X of primary goods like for a pair of nailed boots; less would be useless and more pointless.

 

3.4.9 If, in addition, they knew that opting for a society with a maximin-governed distribution of primary goods (income) would in fact produce for its least-advantaged members the critical stipend X, they would choose it regardless of the relative probabilities of getting a bigger, equal or smaller stipend in other kinds of societies. If worse alternatives are simply unacceptable
and better ones leave you cold, it could not possibly matter how probable they are. Your maximand is discontinuous. It is the single number X. If you can get it at all, you take it. Talking of a "maximin" strategy and of "choice in the face of uncertainty" is the very paradigm of the red herring.

 
  1. (What happens if a maximin-principled society turns out not to be rich enough to assure for everybody a high enough minimum stipend, such as X, sufficient to let them fulfil their life-plans? Rawls is satisfied that since such a society is both reasonably just and reasonably efficient, it can safely guarantee X for everybody [pp. 156 and 169]; the certitude of X, then, is a preferred alternative to facing incertitude.
  2.  
  3. This, of course, is as it may be. A society may be efficient, yet quite poor-the successive Prussias of Frederick William I and of Erich Honecker would probably both fit this bill-and people in the original position have no clue whether the efficient and just society they are about to devise might not be quite poor, too. James Fishkin takes the view that if a society can guarantee everybody's satisfactory minimum, it is a society of abundance "beyond justice."*39 On the other hand, if the stipend guaranteed by enacting maximin fell short of the critical X, people could not both regard the meagre guaranteed stipend as one they "can hardly accept" yet rationally choose it in preference to non-guaranteed, uncertain but more acceptable alternatives.)
  4.  
  5. If uncertainty is to be something more in Rawls's theory than a redundant catch-word, a passport to the fashionable land of decision theory, his life-plan and his two psychological assumptions about the minimum stipend (i.e. that less is

unacceptable and more unnecessary) must not be taken literally. Though primary goods fulfil "needs and not desires," we must firmly recall that they are consumable goods and not tools; that no matter how little or how much of them people have, they are never indifferent to having more; and that there is no significant discontinuity, no void above and below the satisfactory minimum stipend, but rather an intense "need" for primary goods below and a less intense "need" above it, so that the index of primary goods becomes a proper maximand, a fairly closely spaced schedule of alternative numbers, fit to be ordered consistently, instead of one lonely number. Rawls wishes the theory of justice to be a particular application of the theory of rational choice; if his assumptions are taken at face value, all occasion for choice is shut out in advance; we must interpret them more loosely so that they leave room for genuine alternatives.*40

 
  1. Having done so, we find that we have in fact glimpsed the outline of the utility function of the people concerned (despite Rawls's protestations that they behave as if they had none). It conforms to the conventional supposition of diminishing marginal utility at least in the neighbourhood of a level X of primary goods. (There is a presumption, arising from Rawls's remarks, that it conforms to it in more distant ranges, too.) If people were oblivious of this, they could not be conscious of the greater or lesser acceptability of various stipends of primary goods, and would not feel an imperative "need" to get at least so much, nor a much less compelling "need" to get more. Unless they had some such awareness of the relative intensity of their "needs" (or desires?), they could not rationally evaluate mutually exclusive uncertain prospects of getting different lots of primary goods, except for judging that one prospect was infinitely valuable and the others were worthless.
  2. Consider next Rawls's first psychological assumption about "sharply discounting estimates... of probabilities" (p. 154). People (still in the original position) are required to choose between principles which determine types of society, which in turn entail particular income distributions, under each of which they could find themselves drawing any one of the different lots of primary goods which reward differently situated people in that type of society. They can, as we know, choose an equal distribution, or maximin (likely involving some inequality), or one of a possibly large number of feasible distributions, many of which will be more inegalitarian than maximin.*41 We also know that maximin dominates equality,*42 i.e. that no rational and non-envious person will choose the latter if he can choose the former. Other than that, however, the mere requirement of rationality leaves the remaining choices wide open as between maximin and more unequal distributions. People are uncertain what their own lot would be in each, and have no objective data at all for guessing. They are, nonetheless, said to choose one and take their chances under it.
  3.  
  4. Since they are rational, the distribution they do choose must have the property that the utilities of the alternative lots that can be drawn under it, each multiplied by the probability (0 = 1) of drawing that particular lot, yield a larger total sum than would any other feasible distribution. (For "yield" one may wish to substitute "are thought to yield.") This is merely a corollary of the definition of rationality. In technical language, we would say "it is analytic that the rational man maximizes the mathematical expectation of utility."*43 The limiting case of uncertainty is certainty, where the probability of drawing a given lot is 1 and that of drawing any other lot is 0. The rational man can then be said to be simply maximizing utility and never mind its probability.
  5. Rawls is free to assert that his parties are "sceptical" and "wary of probability calculations" (pp. 154-5). If they do choose in the face of uncertainty, which is what they have been put in the original position to do, their choices amount to imputing probabilities to outcomes, no matter whether they do it sceptically, confidently, anxiously or in any other state of emotion. We are even free to insist that they do no such thing. All that matters is that their behaviour would make sense if they did. If their conduct cannot be described in such terms, the assumption of their rationality must be given up. We can say, for instance, that people attach a probability of 1 to drawing the worst lot and probabilities smaller than 1 but greater than 0 to drawing each of the better lots; but we cannot in the same breath say that they are rational. If they were, they would not implicitly contradict the axiom that the odds of drawing all the lots add up to one.
  6.  
  7. It is easy enough to accept that if rational people were certain of drawing the worst lot under any income distribution, they would choose the one which had the "best worse" (maximin). This would always be the best play in a game where they could choose the distribution and the opposing player (their "enemy") could assign them their place within it, for he would be sure to assign them the worst one.*44 Rawls says both that people in the original position reason as if their enemy was going to assign them their lot (p. 152), and that they should not reason from false premises (p. 153). Presumably, the fiction of an enemy is intended to convey, without quite saying so, that people act as if they imputed a probability of 1 to the worst lot. In fact, maximin is designed to deal with the assumed certainty that our opponent will make moves that help him most and hurt us worst, but conveying this without saying so does not make the idea sensible in a situation

where there is no enemy, no competing player, no opposing will, in short, where there is no game, only gratuitously introduced game-theory language.

 
  1. Each person in the original position knows without a doubt that any unequal distribution of lots must by its nature contain some lots that are better than the worst one, and that some people will draw them. What can make him sure that he won't? He has "no objective ground," nor any other cause for reasonable belief, that he has no chance of being one of these people. But if the better lots do have non-zero probabilities, the worst one cannot have a probability of 1, or else the odds would not add up. Hence whatever rational people may choose in the original position, they do not choose maximin except by a fluke (in the course of "randomizing" in a mixed strategy?), so that the likelihood of unanimous choice is as good as nil and the theory is aground.*45
  2.  
  3. A straightforward way to refloat it would be to jettison rationality. This would be all the more tempting as real people are not obliged to be rational. They are quite capable of tying themselves up in amazing logical inconsistencies. They can both accept and contradict a given axiom (such as the one that if one outcome is certain, the others must be impossible). Freed of the harsh and perhaps unrealistic discipline of rationality, they can be supposed to behave any way the theorist may fancy. (For instance, in his numerous writings on the theory of risky choices, G. L. S. Shackle substituted poetic and pretty suggestions about human nature in place of the arid calculus of probability and utility. The "liquidity preference" of Keynesian economics is at bottom also a resort to suggestive poetry. Many theories of producers' behaviour rely on assumptions of non-rationality-full cost pricing, "growth" and market share objectives, rather than profit maximization, are well
BOOK: The State by Anthony de Jasay
3.28Mb size Format: txt, pdf, ePub
ads

Other books

Ravensclaw by Maggie MacKeever
Ten Thumb Sam by Rachel Muller
Allegra by Shelley Hrdlitschka
School of Charm by Lisa Ann Scott
The Wicker Tree by Robin Hardy
The Intruders by Michael Marshall
Blood on Biscayne Bay by Brett Halliday
Mostly Monty by Johanna Hurwitz