I confess to being in love with that definition
13
âwhich in fact quite accurately describes classic Aristotelian dramaturgy. The “unstable homeostatic system” is what I've called elsewhere the Ground Situation of any story: a dramaturgically voltaged state of affairs pre-existing the story's present action, like the ongoing feud between the Capulets and the Montagues. Its “incremental perturbation” is the “rising action” or complications of the conflict following upon the introduction of a Dramatic Vehicle into the Ground Situation (Romeo Montague and Juliet Capulet fall into star-crossed love, a turn of events that precipitates Bandello's tale and Shakespeare's play out of the Ground Situation; the couple's incrementally more desperate attempts to consummate that love comprise the story's action). The “catastrophic restoration” is the climax or Aristotelian
peripateia
, catastrophic in its relative swiftness and magnitude even in the quietest of stories. And the “complexified equilibrium” thereby restored is the classic denouement, dramaturgically consequential vis-Ã -vis the original Ground Situation or else no story has been told or sung or written down or played out (the lovers' death, e.g., puts the interfamily squabble at least temporarily on Hold).
All that sort of thing really does go without saying for most storytellers, who work at least as much by the hunch and feel of experienced talent as by articulated theory, and who are likely to find it easier to make up a story than to explain the difference between stories and non-stories or not-quite stories. If such high-tech theorizing makes no more sense to you than, say, much of life does, then I offer you another pet maxim from my inventory, to wit:
Of of what
one can't make sense, one may make art.
May I repeat those eleven quasi-stammering monosyllables?
Of of what one can't make sense, one may make art.
O self-demonstrating bliss.
Â
BUT WHY
does
one make art? Specifically, what accounts for the odd circumstance that people in every time and place appear to enjoy, whether as individuals or as cultures, making up non-factual yarns, for example, and telling or writing or acting them out and hearing or reading or spectating them? Why is it that we
Homo sapiens
pleasure in the incremental perturbation of imaginary unstable homeostatic systems and their catastrophic restoration to complexified equilibria? In the vicarious turning of screws on cooked-up predicaments until those quantitative increments effect a comparatively sudden and significant qualitative change?
Damned if I know. In the Friday-piece mentioned above (“It Goes Without Saying”), I itemized some two dozen of fiction's feasible functions, from reality-testing and -mapping to reality-avoidance, from aphrodisia through anaphrodisia to mere linguistical futzing around. Behind all of those catalogued functions, I believe (as well as any of the many that I no doubt missed), lies a neuroscientific argument that strikes me as both plausible and pleasing, and with which I'll close my spiel. The self-styled “neurophilosopher” Daniel C. Dennett, of Tufts University, maintains that human consciousness itself has an essentially narrative aspect, grounded in the biological evolution of the brain. I won't attempt here to summarize Dennett's thesis, but I am immediately persuaded of its validityâat least as an explanatory fiction. To me it seems a short and plausible step, though a consequential and doubtless an intricate one, from the “if”
propositions characteristic of computer and neural programmingâ
If x, then y
, et cetera, which in animal behavior might be called the Four F-propositions: whether Stimulus or Situation X prompts one to Flee, Fight, Feed, or, you know, Mateâit's a short and plausible step, I was saying, from these to the
what if
s and
as if
s of fictional narrative. I second the motion that the “neural Darwinism” by which consciousness may evolveâevolve not only to recognize and act upon stimuli but to reflect upon, disport with, and be moved to aesthetic pleasure by certain of themâhas an inherently narrative aspect. Professor Dennett goes even further, conceiving of consciousness as essentially a “multi-draft scenario-spinner,” or “Joycean machine”; of the self itself as an
as if
, a “posited Center of Narrative Gravity”âin short, as an intricate, on-spinning fiction. “We
are
the stories we tell ourselves and others about who we are,” he concludes (in his treatise
Consciousness Explained
14
): stories that we edit continually, and that continually edit us.
Amen to that, say I. Whether or not one goes the whole way with Dennett's neurophilosophy (and some very prominent neuroscientists do not), he has I think established at very least that when we make up stories or take pleasure in made-up stories, we are literally doing what comes naturally.
Â
NOW, THEN, I ask you: Did the pondering of questions like these ever make anybody a better writer? Wouldn't any fictionist be just as well off following the example of Norman Mailer, say, who in his 1984 Hopwood Lecture declared his tendency “to mumble about technical matters like an old mechanic”? “âLet's put the thingamajig before the whoosits here,'” said Mailer, “is how I usually state the deepest literary problems to myself.” Same here, more often than
not, when I am in actual intimate congress with the muse. It's in the recovery-time between such sessions that I incline to put such questions more formally to myself and to entertain them from others. And I happen to believe that when we do
that
, too, we're doing what comes naturallyâperhaps more naturally to some people than to others.
But I suppose that that goes without saying.
Any further questions?
Incremental Perturbation
Some further “Further Questions.” This little essayâwritten for and first published in an anthology on fiction-writing compiled by one of my former graduate students
1
âshould be skipped by any who've heard enough already about the mechanics of storytelling.
Â
Â
W
hat's a story?
Storytellers (it goes without saying) tell stories. Fiction-writers write them; playwrights and screenwriters script them; opera singers sing them; balletists dance them; mimes mime them. But what's a story?
Damned if I know, for sure. “A whole action, of a certain magnitude,” says Aristotle in effect in his
Poetics
. “A meaningful series of events in a time sequence,” say Cleanth Brooks and Robert Penn Warren in their New-Critical textbook
Understanding Fiction
.
Yes, well. But . . .
Most working writers of fictionâmyself included when the muse and I are at itâoperate less by articulated narrative theory than by the hunch and feel of experience: our experience of successfully (sometimes unsuccessfully) composing, revising, and editing our own stories and, prerequisite to that, our experience of the tens of thousands of stories that all of us audit, read, spectate, and more or less
assimilate in the course of our lives. But it's another matter when, as teachers of novice fiction-writers and coaches of more advanced apprentices in the art, we find ourselves in the position of trying to explain to them and to ourselves why the manuscript before us, whatever its other merits, lacks something that we've come to associate with
stories
, and is in our judgment the less satisfying for that lack. “Gets off on the wrong foot,” somebody in the room may opine. “Something askew in the middle there. . . .” “The
ending
bothers me. . . .”
Okay: But exactly what
about
the beginning, the middle, the ending, fails to satisfy? What keeps the thing from achieving proper storyhood? Freud remarks that he didn't start out with such peculiar notions as the Oedipus Complex; that he was driven to their articulation by what he was hearing from the psychoanalytical couch. That's how I feel with respect to dramaturgical theory.
What's dramaturgy?
In my shop, “dramaturgy” means the management of plot and action; the architecture of Story, as distinct from such other fictive goodies as Language, Character, Setting, and Theme. Be it understood at the outset that
mere
architectural completeness, mere storyhood, doth not an excellent fiction make. Every competent hack hacks out complete stories; structural sufficiency is hackhood's first requirement. On the other hand, about a third of Franz Kafka's splendid fictions, for example, and a somewhat smaller fraction of Donald Barthelme's, happen to be “mere” extended metaphors rather than storiesâmetaphors elaborated to a certain point and then, like lyric poems, closedâand they are no less artistically admirable for that.
2
Such exceptions notwithstanding, the fact is that most of the fiction we admire is admirable dramaturgically as well as in its other aspects.
If we admire a piece of prose fiction despite its non-storyhood, we are, precisely, admiring it
despite
its non-storyhood. Even the late John Gardnerâby all accounts a splendid writing teacher despite his cranky notions of “moral fiction”âused to advise, “When in doubt, go for dramaturgy.” Amen to that.
Back to Aristotle: The distinction between Plot and Action can be useful to what we might call clinical dramaturgical analysis, since a story's problems may lie in the one but not the other. As a classroom exercise, one can summarize the story of Sophocles's
Oedipus the King
, for example, entirely in terms of its plot with little or no reference to its action: “A happily married and much-respected head of state comes to learn that his eminent position is owing to his having unwittingly broken two major-league taboos, and in a day his fortunes are reversed.” Clearly, any number of imaginable sequences of action might body forth that summarized plot. One then proceeds to examine for efficiency and effect the particular sequence chosen by Sophocles to do the job. Indeed, one may summarize the drama contrariwise, entirely in terms of its action with little or no reference to its plot: “A delegation of Theban elders complains to King Oedipus that a plague has fallen upon the place. The King sends his brother-in-law to the Delphic oracle to find out what's going on. That emissary returns with news of the gods' displeasure. The chorus of elders sings and dances apprehensively,” et cetera.
Aristotle's stipulations that the action be 1) “whole” and 2) “of a certain magnitude” can be at least marginally useful, too: A “whole” action includes everything necessary to constitute a meaningful story and excludes anything irrelevant theretoâgot that? “Of a certain magnitude” means that the action of fiction ought not to be inconsequential, however much it might appear to the characters to be so.
But if we ask “What's the meaning of
meaningful
?” or “What do you mean by
consequential
?”, it turns out that
meaningful
means “
dramaturgically
meaningful” and
consequential
means “
dramaturgically
consequential,” and around we go (likewise with Brooks and Warren's “meaningful series of events,” even without their redundant “in a time sequence”). One is tempted to chuck the whole question and go back to good old Hunch and Feelâbut these preliminary distinctions and definitions are worth bearing in mind as we try to spiral out of their circularity, mindful that what we're interested in here is not “mere” theory, but practical dramaturgy: Applied Aristotle.
The curve of dramatic action.
Not all fictive action is dramatic, either in the colloquial sense of “exciting” or in the practical sense of advancing the story's plot. And drama, to be sure, involves those other elements aforementionedâcharacter and theme and language as well as actionâalthough it's worth remembering that the Greek word
drama
literally means “deed,” an action performed by a character, and that Aristotle declares in effect that it's easier to imagine a drama without characters
3
than one without action, the without-which-nothing of story. Dramatic action is conventionally described as “rising” to some sort of climactic “peak” or turning-point and then “falling” to some sort of resolution, or denouement. In short, as a sort of triangleânot really of the isosceles variety sometimes called “Fichte's triangle” after the late-18th-century German philosopher, but more like a stylized profile of Gibraltar viewed (in left-to-right cultures, anyhow) from the west:
. A ramp, let's say, which the story's “rising action” rather gradually ascends to a peak and then precipitately descends (punch lines are normally shorter than their jokes). Add to this ramp a bit of an approach and a bit of an exitâ
âand you've
graphed the Ingredients of Story as conventionally formulated:
Exposition
(the information requisite to understanding the action, or, as I prefer to put it, the “ground situation”: a dramatically voltaged state of affairs pre-existing the story's present time),
Conflict
(or, in my shop, the introduction of the “dramatic vehicle”: a present-time turn of events that precipitates a story out of the ground situation),
Complication
(of which more presently),
Climax
,
Denouement
, and
Wrap-Up
(the little coda, closing fillip, or dolly-back shot often appended to the denouement like a jazz drummer's “roll-off” at the end of a number, and usually suggestive of what the story's completed action
portends
for the principal characters).